ページの画像
PDF
ePub

more strictly to responsibility for negligence in its care and management. This is undoubtedly one of the directions in which we may expect to see great development in the future; for nothing can shock one's sense of justice more than the decisions which, up to the present time, have been so common, holding that, simply because a piece of property, owned by a municipal corporation and negligently managed by it to the damage of an individual, is used for purposes of general rather than of local government, therefore, the municipal corporation which is guilty of the negligence shall be exempted from all liability to the individual for the damages which it has caused.

Mr. Jones also has much to say with regard to the rule which exempts municipal corporations from liability for negligence in the performance of acts which are ultra vires. He considers, as most people consider, that such a rule is unjust, and is indeed nothing but an application of the old idea, which has long since been discarded, that corporations could not be held liable for torts, inasmuch as they in no circumstances are authorized to commit torts and that therefore, the act of the agent by whom the tort was committed is not the act of the corporation. Mr. Jones lays great stress upon a case in the United States Supreme Court, viz., Salt Lake City vs. Hollister (118 U. S., 256). In this case the city was held responsible for the payment of internal revenue taxes incurred by carrying on the business of distilling spirits, although the prosecution of the business was wholly ultra vires. In Mr. Jones's opinion the basis of this decision was the broad ground that corporations could not escape from liability for wrongful acts by showing that these acts were ultra vires, and he believes that Justice Miller, who rendered the opinion in the case, meant to give a deliberate expression of the view of the court upon the general question of ultra vires. It is to be hoped with Mr. Jones, that the decision to which he refers may be given a wider application in the future than it has yet received.

Mr. Jones's style is excellent, and the whole arrangement of the work is so clear that it is a positive pleasure to read it. Higher praise could hardly be given to any legal treatise; for in general such works consist so much of citations from decisions that to any but a lawyer who is endeavoring to write a brief, the perusal of them is altogether wearisome.

F. J. GOODNOW.

Tratado de Derecho Politico. Por ADOLFO POSADA, Profesor en la Universidad de Oviedo. Tomo Primero: Teoria del Estado. Madrid, Libreria de Victoriano Suarez, 1893. — 426 pp.

[ocr errors]

This volume is a welcome contribution to political science. What Bluntschli has done for German, and Burgess and Woolsey for English-American, Posada has begun for Spanish political philosophy. Posada has been a close student of Bluntschli, Spencer, Ihering, Giner and Burgess, following in the main the method of Bluntschli's Theory of the State. While he is indebted to Spencer in the department of sociology, he combats the Englishman's individualistic conceptions. A special feature of the work is the steady use the author makes of the historical method, and his copious references to the literature of the subject. The bibliographical appendix renders the work most valuable as a book of reference to the original authorities, both on the general subject and on the special topics of the various chapters.

The present work is intended to be the first part of a comprehensive treatise on political science and public law. The title, Derecho Politico, of which the nearest English equivalent is "political law," is used to include both the theory of the state, treated in the present volume, and constitutional law, the prospective title of volume second. The concept of the state, its origin and its nature, the author holds, must first be considered, because it is only by a study of these in the light of modern sociology that we can reach the social character of the state in its juridical aspect. In the second part he proposes to complete the consideration of public law by a comparative study of constitutional law and the philosophical theories involved in the constitutions of the principal states of Europe and America.

Posada's exposition of the ultimate nature of the state exhibits the modern historical and sociological spirit. He gives full weight to the results of recent investigations into the characteristics of primitive society, as well as to developments of political history among the civilized peoples of the earth. The evolution of political society is not identical, he holds, though it is parallel, with that of the family. One is as necessary and inevitable as the other, though each is the outcome of a distinct necessity of human life. As one is related to the facts of sexual union and blood relationship, the other rests on social union and common needs and desires. But while political society is an outcome of inherent qualities of man as a material being, the state cannot be conceived as a mere mechanical or physio

logical result of natural agencies; nor, on the other hand, must it be conceived as a pure product of the human will. It is a sociological product of both physical nature and human volition. It answers to an external as well as to an internal necessity; for it is impossible to conceive a state apart from a basis in physical nature, and this implies geographic adaptation. This adaptation, which defines the social groups, according to Burgess, in "geographic and ethnic unities," limits the completer historical manifestation of the state. It conditions the state's action in the sphere of law. The nation, therefore, considered as an expression of these unities, cannot be regarded as necessarily the final manifestation of the state.

The federal state is considered by the author to be the most perfect of the forms of union through which the evolution of political society proceeds. The underlying principle of such a state is not the compact out of which the union takes form, but the existence of a historically-developed people prior to the pact. Where the compact is the primary source of the union, there is a confederation of states, not a federal state. The latter, to use Brunialti's classification, represents a juridical-organic, the former only a historicalpolitical union. The juridical-organic conception is essential to the state in its fullest definition.

In defining the end of the state Posada makes clear the distinction between state and government. The end of the state is the realization of justice. In pursuance of this end, it is the function of the state to determine by law the juridical relations which shall exist between employer and employee, or between state and municipality, or in the sphere of public morality and education. The scope of state activity is made by the author rather wide, though subject always to the limitations of justice.

But it is not to the government that is ascribed the manifestation of all the power that is inherent in the state. Posada sees in the governmental organization but one element of the many through which the state is revealed. His treatment of the function of public opinion in the evolution and action of the state is abreast of the best modern thought on the subject, and there is sound and suggestive political science in his contention that the electoral franchise, far from containing the essence of political power, is but one mode, and not necessarily the most perfect or the most effective, of condensing public opinion. It is easy enough, when attention is called to the matter, to recall any number of instances in which the social force has been concentrated and given direction by the government

or the press or by other means, long before the lagging electoral machinery has expressed the feeling of that part of the state which has the right to vote.

In his discussion of the modern state forms Posada adopts the now common classification of republics and monarchies, subdivided into the parliamentary and the presidential types. His work is a valuable evidence of the spread of sound ideas in political science. J. M. LITTLEJOHN.

COLUMBIA COLLEGE.

By GEORGE

The Development of the Athenian Constitution.
WILLIS BOTSFORD, Ph.D. Cornell Studies in Classical Philology,
No. IV. Boston, Ginn & Co., 1893. — 249 pp.

This is a volume constructed on a system. The author has a thorough belief in the continuity of Aryan tradition in the various cognate races, and feels confident that he may justly predicate of Greece a custom or usage which he finds among the Hindoos, if it bears a primitive character. The principle has been used and abused before. Fustel de Coulanges, Schrader and others have used it; our author thinks that it has been abused when it has been extended beyond the Aryan peoples, and made the basis for inferences from any barbarous tribes, without regard to their nationality, their origin or their habitation. Apparently he will not admit that human nature is largely the same under primitive conditions, and that it works its way from infancy to settled age along lines that are similar because they are human.

In order to carry out his system to a logical conclusion he lays the foundation of the Athenian constitution by tracing the primitive customs and usages of the Aryan peoples, especially the Hindoos, the South Slavonians, the Romans and the Greeks, and he devotes a chapter to the "Patriarchal Theory," another to the "Aryan Gens,” a third to the" Grecian Gens," and a fourth to the "Phratry and Phyle," before beginning definitely upon the Athenians. Here the general principles are secured which are to solve the intricacies and the doubts, and to supply the lack of information, which have been the torment and the despair of many a historian. In some respects it recalls the royal road built from capitol to capitol without swerving a hair's breadth from the straight line, and without regard to towns that lay off its route. It has its advantages for the through traveler, but it presents some difficulties to the one who wishes to take in the whole district. Not that exception can be taken to this

comparative method as a whole. It is one of the greatest of factors in all scientific labor. It is employed here, too, with ingenuity, learning and a wide grasp of the subject. It brings illumination to many dark places, and sets forth the results of many treatises with perspicuity. However, there is a tendency at times to draw conclusions which remain doubtful, and to force analogies which are not justified by the evidence. An example may be instanced in the assumption that there existed a body of clients in Attica which Solon freed, and which are to be compared with the serfs of Gortyna. The theory is not new, but its supporters are rare.

In addition to the Aryan analogies brought to bear upon the constitution of Athens, the author has utilized the material which recently came to hand in the Aristotelian treatise on that constitution. This he rightly accepts as a genuine work of the great philosopher, Draconian chapter and all. This part of our book constitutes one of its chief merits, for it digests in convenient and well-weighed form the results which are to be obtained from this invaluable treasure. Stopping at the Peloponnesian War, our author does not follow Aristotle to the conclusion of his work, but the main substance is covered, as the constitution was fairly established by 430. The book is a distinct addition to our sources for study, and is suggestive even where one may not agree with its conclusions. A. C. MERRIAM.

COLUMBIA COLLEGE.

Labor and the Popular Welfare. By W. H. MALLOCK. London, A. and C. Black, 1893. — 12mo, xi, 336 pp.

Mr. Mallock discusses the social claims of the masses from the standpoint, practically, of the modern English economists. First dismissing socialistic schemes for a new and equal distribution of the national wealth or income, by pointing out their physical impossibility, he shows further the ridiculous consequences of more moderate proposals in this direction. The rentals of the landed aristocracy, for instance, would, if divided, give each man twopence a day, while the monarchy costs each inhabitant less than sixpence halfpenny a year, "the price of drinking the queen's health in a couple of pots of porter."

The striking features of the analysis of production which follows are the clever use of income tax statistics and the emphasis laid upon ability rather than labor as a factor of industrial progress. The causes of the progressive production of wealth are land, capital

« 前へ次へ »